In the early stage of his work, Max Horkheimer (1895-1973) was influenced by the philosophical anthropology of Max Scheler (1874-1928). Accepting this in a critical sense, Horkheimer then constructed his own method of critical theory. He clearly pointed out that Scheler's method rests on deductions drawn from a general image of human nature. In Horkheimer's view, the image of human nature is constantly subjected to historical changes in the value of human society, hence it cannot be fixed or an absolute. In contrast to proponents of modern metaphysics, Horkheimer took pains to emphasise the “function” of value in thought. The methodology of his “dialectical anthropology” is based on the idea that human images are determined, above all, by the “transitory” [vergänglich] aspirations of human beings to happiness and freedom, rather than by a stable and unchanging essential relationship [Wesenszusammenhang] of value.
Following another line of development, we find that Arnold Gehlen (1904-1976), the leading postwar philosophical anthropologist, was also influenced by Scheler's thought. Gehlen, however, based his anthropology not on metaphysics, but on empirical sciences, such as behaviour theory. In addition, he criticized the Marxist theory of alienation, which presupposes that all subjects have a tendency, or a natural right, to demand the reclamation of their own individual products. Dismissing the ideological implications of this alienation theory, Gehlen attempted to recast it into a neutral and psychological form. According to his own account, his anthropology was based on the following ideas : that industrial society had been transformed from pure capitalism to a welfare-state situation, and, further, that the foundation for human life lies in the stability of social institutions. Human beings can realize their desires only by means of social institutions, which alter the immediate nature of these desires into a mediated and durable form.
Comparing Horkheimer (along, generally speaking, with related schools established by critical theorists, including Adorno) on the one hand with Gehlen on the other, we are struck by the co-existence of points both of divergence and of similarity. One significant area of difference lies in their contrasting evaluations of human freedom or of autonomy. Whereas Adorno maintained that “dialectical exchange [Auseinandersetzung] between society and individuals” enables people to “go beyond the stage of monadological existence,” Gehlen accepted the behaviour theory that assumes arbitrary control of the human mind to be possible. Nonetheless, they both shared the view that human reason is not so strong as it is assumed to be in Scheler's classical-modem theory of human existence. In reference to this departure from Scheler, we may thus classify their approaches under the heading of “anthropologies of the postwar generation.” Scheler actually suggested the limit of the theory of the autonomous individual in Kant's practical philosophy, and this in spite of the fact that schools of critical theory and philosophical anthropology after World War II tended to confuse a popularized image of strong individuals in industrial society with Scheler's human image. In “The Status of human nature in the cosmos [Die Stellung des Menschen im Kosmos]” (1928), an article written in his last years, Scheler dismissed not only a one-sided assumption of strong human nature, but also the metaphysical idea of “mind/body” dualism. In their place, he propounded a new dualism of “spirit/life,” grounded on the idea that the human spirit [der Geist] has, essentially, no powers to “create [schaffen]” need nor to control them directly. A “special position [Sonderstelle]” of human nature lies solely in the ultimate independence of the human spirit from psychological and physical wants.
(View PDF for the rest of the abstract.)
View full abstract